Thursday, February 24, 2022

Libertarian Anglican II: Passive Obedience, Non-Juror, and Christian Resistance

In morality the eternal rules of action have the same immutable universal truth with propositions in geometry. Neither of them depends on circumstances or accidents, being at all times and in all places, without limitation or exception, true. ' Thou shalt not resist the supreme civil power ' is no less constant and unalterable a rule, for modelling the behaviour of a subject toward the government, than 'multiply the height by half the base' is for measuring a triangle. And, as it would not be thought to detract from the universality of this mathematical rule that it did not exactly measure a field which was not an exact triangle, so ought it not to be thought an argument against the universality of the rule prescribing passive obedience that it does not reach a man's practice in all cases where a government is unhinged, or the supreme power disputed. There must be a triangle, and you must use your senses to know this, before there is room for applying your mathematical rule. And there must be a civil government, and you must know in whose hands it is lodged, before the moral precept takes place. But, where the supreme power is ascertained, we should no more doubt of our submission to it, than we would doubt of the way to measure a figure we know to be a triangle.
 
In the Various Changes and Fluctuations of Government, it is impossible to prevent that Controversies shou'd sometimes arise concerning the Seat of the Supreme Power. And in such Cases Subjects cannot be Denied the Liberty of Judging for Themselves, or of taking part with some, and opposing others, according to the best of their Judgments; all which is Consistent with an exact Observation of their Duty, so long as, when the Constitution is clear in the Point, and the Object of their Submission undoubted, no Pretext of Interest, Friends, or the Publick Good, can make them depart from it. In short, it is acknowledged, that the Precept enjoyning Non-Resistance is Limited to particular Objects, but not to particular Occasions. And in this it is like all other Moral Negative Duties, which consider'd as general Propositions, do admit of Limitations and Restrictions, in order to a distinct Definition of the Duty; but what is once known to be a Duty of that sort, can never become otherwise by any good or ill Effect, Circumstance, or Event whatsoever. And in Truth if it were not so, if there were no General Inflexible Rules, but all Negative as well as Positive Duties might be Dispensed with, and Warpt to Serve particular Interests and Occasions, there were an end of all Morality. (Berkeley, Discourse of Passive Obedience, LIII-LIV)

These concluding arguments were how George Berkeley, a lowly Anglo-Irish priest, concluded his defense of passive obedience. A doctrine made a shibboleth for all High Churchmen, Tories waived it proudly in their loud cries that the Church was in danger. And in the early eighteenth century, this was, at best, only partially true. Nevertheless, the ambiguity of this cry to honor the supreme magistrate created consternation among the government. It was a call that was ambiguous, especially as the throne itself was contested. According to Berkeley's logic, this meant that an Anglican Christian could be faithful through obedience to both the Jacobean Stuarts or the new Hanoverian dynasty. And more importantly, it did not, by necessity, include the ministers of the king. Were they, exactly, executing his will? It had been a long time trope that the evils of the realm may be products of wicked scheming counselors. But for those who held the purse-strings of the Kingdom, the mercantile-inclined land magnates of Parliament, what level of protection did they have? Per Berkeley, it was entirely reasonable to resist laws which had no basis in legitimacy. And thus poor George, a favorite of Queen Caroline's and in her Enlightened republic of letters, lost many opportunities of preferment. While Berkeley would ascend to the bishopric of Cloyne in the Church of Ireland (a modest appointment), he would never attract the support necessary for his missionary college in the Americas or his efforts to reform Ireland's economic situation.

This essay is the second part of a dialectical discussion of Anglican "libertarianism" that begun first with a reconstruction of Benjamin Hoadly's Whiggish defense of conscience. To telegraph where this essay will head, we will see the Enlightened vision of Hoadly's intractable foes: the Non-Jurors. They will hammer at the joints of Hoadly's schema, which will leave him open to serious criticism. Caught between the radical Hookerian whiggery of Hoadly and the Non-Juror's rival vision, many High Churchmen will hedge their bets in siege mode (in both their Tory and Court Whig factions) for their corporate privileges. They will come to terms with Parliament's increasing dominance over the affairs of Great Britain, which saw material flourishing (even if provoking a greater threat of spiritual depravity). This essay is not about them, a history which is familiar to most students of the Church of England (especially in its dramatic revision from enflamed pens of Victorian Evangelicals and Anglo-Catholics). This essay is, instead, a defense of Passive Obedience as a means to resist unjust, illicit, and, even, wicked government from the truculent defenders of the Church. This essay is about the Non-Jurors.

A quick history of the Non-Juror schism:

The Restoration (1660/62) saw many churchmen rejoice as they returned from exile. Priests had to memorize the prayerbook to avoid Cromwellian Triers (a state lay oversight board of England's many, puritanized, parishes). Many fled to France with uncrowned Stuart heir. The Restoration of the Church under Charles II's Cavalier Parliament restored the ecclesiastical program of King Charles and Archbishop William Laud with vengeance. Charles II's pledge of toleration, in the Declaration of Breda, was tossed aside. Refusal to conform to the restored prayerbook saw the ejection of many puritan ministers, beginning their transformation into Dissent. However, this restored Church did not correct the governmental deficiencies which beset the Church before the Civil Wars. A few "high fliers" were concerned the spiritual ministry of the Church was hampered through a lack of independency and a wooden diocesan structure for bishops. But they mainly kept silent before the laicizing Laudian Parliament, which fought vigorously for their interests. They would, in general, form the ecclesiastical core of Tories, defending royal power against Parliament's bid to reject James II's succession in the Exclusion Crisis. They stood up for James Stuart, though a papist, out of royal privilege, but they were not cowed. When James overstepped his boundary, requiring the Church to declare toleration from the pulpit, seven bishops stood their ground and refused. In classic practice of passive obedience, they said no and accepted the unjust royal punishment, locked in the Tower of London. Nevertheless, James was still their king. 

When William of Orange (James II's nephew and son-in-law) took up the cause of the beleaguered English nobility, receiving and responding to the request of the Immortal Seven, they maintained their loyalty. James had fled and William, at the head of his four thousand man army, summoned a constitutional convention. The result was the Glorious Revolution, where James had (through a legal fiction) abdicated and William, with his far more legitimate wife Mary, was crowned. Those jailed bishops refused to recognize this turn of events. As William, and his Parliamentary allies, feared instability, new oaths were required. Bishops and the priests loyal to James, per passive obedience, refused and awaited their fate. William sacked them, about four-percent of the clergy, and then, the damning act, replaced them. It was this royal interference in clerical succession, not the oaths or their removal from their places of worship, which triggered the Non-Juror schism.

The Non-Jurors thought William was a usurper and his oaths an unjust imposition. However, these were not sufficient to provoke open conflict with churchmen who conformed to the revolutionary settlement. It was the royal encroachment of ecclesiastical privileges. As Henry Dodwell, doyen of the Non-Jurors and one of their brightest lights, the tradition of St Cyprian of Carthage was normative. The bishop was a spiritual monarch of the Church, who respected the diocesan boundaries of his fellow princes of the Church. For Dodwell, as well as many of his fellow Non-Jurors, this ecclesiastical element set the Reformed Church of England apart from both Rome and the Erastian trends of the Reformation. In the former, the pope usurped episcopal authority through his inflated claims; in the latter, derelict Protestants foolishly handed this authority over to temporal princes. For the Non-Jurors' own accounting (which may or may not be tenuous in its reconstruction) the Church of England understood the firm distinctions between temporal and spiritual power. The monarch was not the head of the Church (despite the Henrician tyranny), but its governor, and this titular authority only applied to the Church's civil affairs. The Church sat its bishops in the House of Lords, it was awarded property,  and it was given money and royal honors. These things the crown governed, with or without Parliament, per its prerogative as supreme magistrate. However, this authority was not spiritual. The Church's mission pertained to the salvation of souls, and how this manifested in the physical and tactile lives of the faithful. This split didn't cut down between inner-invisible and outer-visible, but two missions. Kingdoms were established for temporal peace among men, whereas the Church was established for the development of saints for the Kingdom of God. Dodwell, along with other Cyprianic Non-Jurors, believed the Glorious Revolution had blurred this distinction towards a corrupt Erastian bargain.

Thus, for the Non-Jurors, and some of their High Church (a distinct faction within the Church) admirers, it was precisely out of obedience to the divine constitution of the Church and the temporal authority of the crown that they would resist. Some of their politics resulted in active conspiracy with James II and his son, the Pretender, James III. But mostly it was offering a substantive critique of both politicians and churchmen who could not sufficiently justify the new regime. For Non-Jurors, the path solution was clear. The king and the bishop were parallel sets of authority who had valid succession from their predecessor. As George Hickes, Non-Juror bishop and one of their most authoritative authors, put it: ""as Kings are Bishops of the State, so Bishops are as Kings in the Church" (Two Treatises, 201).

 It was out of this forceful distinction between church and state, on offices identified along lawful possession, that stirred arch-Whig Hoadly. The context for the bishop of Bangor's infamous sermon was his refutation of George Hickes. Hoadly, representing the polar opposite of the Non-Jurors, would not settle for the legal fiction of an abdicated throne. Rather, Hoadly offered a full-throated defense of armed conflict if the king threatened the nation. While his many enemies would denounce old Ben as a Hobbist, a republican, and a regicide, Hoadly was enunciating a view of Parliament that was not unlike Hooker's understanding of how the monarch ruled through Parliament as the collective wisdom of the nation. Hoadly did not advocate democracy or mob politics, swiftly denouncing violence from the rabble. Nevertheless, the proper channels of authority, manifest in the classes represented in both the Lords and the Commons, had the right to defend themselves, their property, and the realm from an overreaching king. Similarly, the Church, as a temporal institution synthesized with the Christian kingdom, had a similar responsibility. The bishops, seated in the upper-house, guided the laws of the kingdom, including doctrinal standards. Hoadly did not deny the tripartite hierarchy of the Church (bishop-priest-deacon) as venerable and preferable in all times. Also, Hoadly did not deny that prior to a kingdom's conversion that the Church stood independently from the other organs of society. Nevertheless, following other so-called "Latitude men", like archbishop Tillotson and bishop Stillingfleet, the integration of the kingdom meant an intermixture of these different organizations. The Church, seated in Parliament and under the governance of the Crown, was part of England's historic constitution, representative of the nation.

In all of the above, Hoadly drew upon the rich legacy of Hookerian polity and ecclesiology. This should be treated with care and respect. Nevertheless, the violent response to Hoadly reflected the changed context of both the English government and the Church of England. Confessionalism had ended in carnage and burnout. Protestants, both Lutheran and Reformed, sought other pathways for both church and state. Leibniz's rationalism was not antithetical, but derivative, of his ecumenical Lutheran faith. The so-called Cambridge Platonists (a far less unified informal network of English Neo-platonic rationalists) were irenic Protestants against materialism and skepticism. The Enlightenment was, in general, a broad movement to deal with the wasteland of the failure of Confessional warfare. The renaissance humanism of Hooker would metastasize into the ecclesiastical thought of Benjamin Hoadly.

Additionally, the framework of government in state and church had changed. Parliament had ceased to be an "event", as it was in Hooker's time, and become an institution. Parliamentary elections were regular and its meeting had become the means for rival visions to be hammered out agonistically through party and faction. The normalization of partisanship still left a very bitter taste in the mouths of many eighteenth-century contemporaries; how much more to Hooker's day and age! Similarly, the ecclesiastical body of Convocation had become the source of increasing strain and stress. Consumed with handling trinitarian heresies, combined with antipathy between the court-inclined episcopal bench and the gentry-inclined presbyterate, saw Convocation ultimately silenced. Hoadly's controversial sermon provoked the backlash and fierce argument which saw Convocation ultimately closed. In the increasingly policed polite polity of Whig-dominated England, institutions which could not control these forces outside the channels of proper aristocratic rule were put aside. Convocation, as a rival and strictly ecclesiastical body, had no place as a rival to the ecclesiastical policies of Parliament. 

However, as should be clear, this silencing of Convocation was not secularization. Rather, it was that Parliament (with its overwhelmingly lay membership) would determine the religious policy of the kingdom. And what would that policy be? In a religiously plural empire, with Presbyterians in Scotland and Northern Ireland, Congregationalists in New England, various rambling enthusiasts in Pennsylvania, Parliament pursued a broad Protestant coalition. With the succession of a former (and nominal) German Lutheran to the throne, and the immigration of Continental Protestants to British North America, the British Empire ("commercial, mercantile, Protestant, and free") became the source of a united front against Rome (particularly in her eldest daughter, France). And if Parliament was to pursue policies representative of this empire, then it would restrain the Church of England from disturbing this balance. However, this restraint was to create a broad Protestant culture out of which churches could generally flourish under a policy of benign neglect. The Church of England never ceased to be the established institution, but it was pushed to be an increasingly broad vehicle of Protestantism (increasingly defined as anti-Rome) throughout the Empire. Long after Hoadly, this ecumenical Protestantism would incorporate any resistance towards the French Revolution and its many aftershocks. This breadth would include the romantic Coleridge and the quasi-Deist Paley.

The purpose of looking down the pipeline is to understand a distinction between Hoadly's doctrine of sincerity and its application. Within this ecumenical Protestant milieu, which primarily sought to incorporate Reformed orthodox and Reformed heterodox (Arminians), one's conscience was free to pursue the truth of things. However, such an arrangement was in no way a step towards "liberalism", defined as the valorization of independent inquiry in any direction whatsoever. Rather, it was out of a concern to secure a broadly Protestant Empire to stand against Catholicism (among other things) that this bounded discourse existed. The point is not, as it is with much uninteresting "critical" historiography, to show that Britain was not so liberal and tolerant as it claimed to be. You can read contemporaries, from both Tories and Whigs outside the halls of power, leveling the same criticism. Rather, the point is to raise a question of how the sincere conscience formed. It's worth noting that Hobbes rejected any coercive measures against the conscience, since laws and force could in no way intrude into the mind (though, per Hobbes' spiritual materialism, outward conformity would eventually produce inner harmony). In short, Hoadly in no way rejected the formative/teaching mission of the Church. The spiritual work of the bishop was to put forth the truth of Scripture, to win and persuade the congregation. However, this itself was bounded. By whom? Parliament, which would form the doctrinal basis of the Church. It could threaten and punish (as it did with the obnoxious Henry Sacheverell for preaching passive obedience) for those outside of its bounds. This formula could guarantee an affable and fair catholicity within the Church, a striking alternative towards any drive towards confessionalism that motivated many Puritans in the previous century (as well as arch-conformists, like Archbishop Whitgift, who wanted a stronger Calvinist orthodoxy in the Church). But its catholicity, its breadth and its limits, would be determined through the Christianized Parliament, which increasingly took up an imperial jurisdiction over the entire Empire.

In the eyes of the Tractarians, who damned Hoadly as a precursor to the Gorham controversy, this arrangement began the necessary spiral into vague utilitarian deism of the English establishment. While the Tractarians' own historiography has been substantially revised (Hoadly's era was not a downward decline or some necessary "Protestantizing" logic unfolded before Leviathan), Hoadly's application of sincerity raises substantial questions: not about the freedom of the conscience, but its molding. If bishops, like Hoadly, depended on Parliamentary support for their office, their teaching would be a product of the regnant Parliamentary consensus. In one way, this approach was not different from the lay rule of the Cavalier Parliament, only that it tolerated broader Protestant movements than those linked strictly to the Laudian Reformed-Patristic theology of the 1662 Prayerbook. In both cases, the shaping of the conscience flowed from the boundaries Parliament determined. And what plan? For most of the Augustan period, the Whig government of Robert Walpole maintained attachment to High Churchmanship, as long as it did not intrude too much into social affairs. But for a few spurts, the aggressive Whig program of Stanhope-Sunderland threatened to strip more prerogatives of the Church (as well as pursue an aggressive militant Continental policy). The latter found support from, and in turn supported, the ministry of Hoadly. Nevertheless, Parliament led the way in forming these mores, even as it left alone many dissenters who raged against this slide into comfortable commercial society.

Non-Jurors, instead, vigorously rebutted Hoadly, and none more famously than William Law. A late-comer to the Non-Juror movement (part of the second-wave during the succession of George I), William Law was a lowly priest and remained so the rest of his life. Law would become renowned as a spiritual authority for his devotional manual (A Serious Call to a Devout and Holy Life), as well his fairly orthodox interpretation of Jakob Boehme's mystical theology. But before all of this, Law's genius shined forth in his response to Hoadly. It was not full of vitriol or heat, but rather a cool response to the proponent of calm and logical preaching.

Law rejected Hoadly's straw-man of the Non-Juror position. The purpose of clerical authority was not to hold the people enslaved to a Romish superstition. Rather, the priestly vocation was installed to bless and reconcile the many peoples into the Church, not to damn or save (Second Letter, 37-38). Like the sacraments, normal elements sanctified for spiritual use, so too did ordination sanctify men for the exercise of God's spiritual government. And since this arrangement, like the sacraments, was from God, no man or power could alter this promise (39-41).  And as the Godman had installed the Apostles, and the Apostles installed the bishops, so too would this copying process continue through the same means. Just as copied Bibles emerged from Bibles, so too did clergy reproduce clergy; they were not a civil order instantiated at will (41-42). Law agreed with Hoadly that the hierarchy had no right to the temporal sword (55-56), but what powers, precisely, did the Church have? Law turned Hoadly's argument around: if ordained spiritual authority took away from God, then did Parliamentary government take away from the king (58-59)? In someway Law's argument fails against Hoadly himself, but it raises more particular questions. Hoadly would've rejected the logic of Law's sacramental comparison because Hoadly opted for something borderline memorialist. The Supper was powerful because it's obedience to God's command to enact a memorial until the Lord comes, but it was not a supreme rite in the life of the Church that communicated any special grace. Similarly, preaching and ministering were faithful obedience to promote faithful living and cultivate virtue. 

Additionally, Hoadly may very well accept that the appointment of ministers limited the king's power, but this was not analogous to Christ, who held direct rule over his subjects. Thus the analogous parallel between the spiritual Kingdom of God and the temporal kingdoms of men was snapped, for God governed in a way very different from men. All secrets, all hearts, all actions were open to God in the way inaccessible to any mere mortal. But one may raise the question of the significance of Christ's continued humanity, his appointment of the Apostles, the importance of forming communities with hierarchs. What kind of authority did they have? If it was mere ability to properly teach and profess the faith, then this raises the kind of authority they had within the Roman Empire. And it was this confusion that Hoadly failed to clarify. On the contrary, Law's Non-Juror ecclesiology made clear the mediated spiritual authority of holy orders.

For Law, Hoadly was not clear or straightforward (virtues he praised) in his applied doctrine of sincerity. The direct rule of Christ was not contradicted through a mediatory priesthood. No Non-Juror believed the priesthood was absolute or could tyrannize the conscience, yet they accepted the clergy did have authority over the conscience. They had a right to pronounce things right or wrong, true or false, about the Kingdom of God. Thus the analogy with civil authority was important for both had their own intrinsic limits (Third Letter, 113-115). For even in a constitutional monarchy, limited by constant consultation with the best (Lords-aristocracy) and many (Commons-democracy), errors and injustices may be made. Hoadly was clear that, out of natural law, a man may disobey a law that would result in his death, the same way a child may fight back against a father seeking to kill him. Contrary to Hoadly, these responses derive out of one's conscience and judgement. Therefore conscience was not strictly spiritual, but pertained to both spiritual and temporal affairs. The difference between spiritual and temporal, if not conscience, "one presides over us in things relating to religion and the service of God, the other presides over us in things relating to civil life" (120).

The fundamental failure for Hoadly, per Law, was his inability to understand spiritual authority as federal. Whatever the merits of Hoadly's doctrine of sincerity, his Hookerian emphasis on an English commonwealth, the interrelatedness of Church and state in a Christian society, Law struck his weakest joint. For Hoadly, even as he was no Lockean, lacked Hooker's Platonic metaphysics and rich sacramental symbolism. Law compared Hoadly's assessment of excommunication to an analysis of Baptism that looked at the chemical composition of water: it missed the point entirely. Excommunication was not a sociological function of group maintenance, it was a covenant sign (143-147). Law confessed that no, spiritual authority has no teeth in this life, but it is the future reality forming the present through an awareness of significance (151-153).  In an analogous situation, the reading out of a law does not have any immediate effect, but a looming shadow of the judgement that would/could come (163-165). In more contemporary terms, a parking ticket is not the judgement itself, but an effective symbol, even a sacrament, of the state according to the law installed. To call a parking ticket a symbol does not remove its force. It summons a sense of dread, frustration, or indignity and will prompt a response to pay or resist. The federal nature of Christian sacraments is their powerful present significance for the shape of time. To simply dismiss the Eucharist as mere symbol, or to diminish holy orders to rhetoric efficacy misses the point. In God's judgement they possess potency, and Christians should honor this as they partake and participate mystically in the New Covenant. Human laws may help shore up the divine reality of the Church, and are mere sign-posts of a deeper truth (181-184). In other terms, a city may up a fence around a ravine to add a layer of signification to the cliff. But the government does not create the symbolic real of height and depth, and it certainly does not legislate the impact of gravity! 

In short, for Law, Hoadly cannot understand the Non-Jurors because he rejected federal theology when it counted most. And his doctrine of sincerity, left to the raging waves of the rapidly developing British Empire, did not provide the necessary bulwark for the Church of England to stand its own particular ground. While Hoadly cannot be blamed for the future, it is easy to trace his Whiggish empiricism (in stark contrast to Bishop Berkeley's empirical-idealism) to the positivistic materialism of the nineteenth-century, an era that saw the vigorous rejection of Hoadly in both the Evangelical and Tractarian movements. And in this way, despite Hoadly's merits, Law the Non-Juror stood as a clarion call of danger.

What does Non-Juror ecclesiology and sincerity have to do with the doctrine of Passive Obedience? Much in every way. Hoadly's defense of the sincere conscience leaves open the question of legitimacy, the same as George Berkeley's conclusion about passive obedience. There are two distinct questions between the moral requirement and its application. And it is in the realm of the conscience where such would be worked out. And what are the broad contours upon which conscience is formed, pressured, and oriented? Should it be a modern state, made up of representatives (a dubious category that requires refinement) of the nation of varied loyalties? Or should it be the hierarchy of the Church? In no way does the latter require slavish obedience to institutional authority. Hoadly and the Non-Jurors, perhaps strangely at first, agree over the freedom of the conscience and the importance of sincerity to make belief meaningful. The Church had no right to cajole and coerce through taxes, fines, and punishments. Nevertheless, the spiritual authority of the Church could impose upon the conscience through the question of excommunication. Contrary to Hoadly's accusations, no Non-Juror ever believed his authority to be absolute; God could always overrule it providentially or at the Last Judgement. However, it's a question of where this power to determine norms be found. Non-Jurors did not advocate laicization or secularity; they were quite comfortable with cooperation between a crown/council with the Church. Nevertheless, these were parallel sets of authority, one eternal and the other temporal, which ought to respect each other's boundaries. It is in this forceful demarcation, which set Non-Jurors as key spiritual ancestors to the American Anglican breakaway, capable of existing through the bishops, without royal (or state) authority whatsoever.

Passive obedience, as a virtue, is precisely in recognizing the alienness of the state (or any other form of temporal governance) from eternal mission of the Church. Christians may thank God for sending a Constantine, who rewards and blesses the Church for fidelity. But such was never normative for understanding either the Church or her mission. Instead, since the eternal precedes the temporal, so too will the Church help shape the conscience through certain moral guidance. And as the Non-Jurors themselves practiced, accepting the temporal punishments of the legitimate civil magistrate may lead to active resistance against illegitimate government or law. It's no surprise that Passive Obedience threatened, not consoled, a sitting regime. For the steeling the nerves of the faithful to witness against evil government or law often did more to topple wicked ministers than active revolt. The Monmouth Rebellion failed, but the Seven Bishops crippled James' absolutism and re-Catholocizing program.

Applied, an Anglican Christian may practice Passive Obedience in refusing to recognize certain government mandates as a legitimate or legal form of authority. One may sincerely refuse unlawful coercive measures, appealed to the legitimate supreme authority (e.g. legislative power of Congress, the Constitution, the People, etc.) Similarly, the logic of Passive Obedience is the virtuous willingness to suffer. It does not conspire or scheme with a certain faction of elites to topple one regime or another. Rather it is a groundswell of resistance, to refuse compliance boldly and accept the penalties meted out. It's no surprise that, in the history of the English church, it was around the flag of the Church that popular disobedience crippled the moral legitimacy or authority of the reigning Parliament. Passive Obedience is not simply an archaic virtue, a way to slavishly grovel before authority, as many critics have offered. Rather it is a fundament for resistance, not out of anarchic willfulness but the authority of Heaven. For when you stand alone, you are not naked before the power of the state, but stand enveloped in a great cloud of witnesses. The promises of God are with you, partaking mystically from the eternally new covenant of the Lamb slain before the Foundation of the World. Let the reality of God's future govern your present. And having stood, stand.

Wednesday, February 23, 2022

Libertarian Anglican I: A Defense of Benjamin Hoadly and Hookerian tradition

Benjamin Hoadly, most infamous as bishop of Bangor, is punished. Touted as the symbol of the spiritual dearth that was the Augustan church, High Churchmen and Evangelicals excoriated the supposedly "Latitudinarian" (read: rationalist or modernist) captivity of the Church. Ministers worried about hobbies and tithes, reduced to employees of the Parliamentary Leviathan, the Hanoverian episcopal bench reflected the stupor of the age. Infatuated with the empirical materialism born of becoming a commercial society, the Church of England had ceased to offer any robust and full-throated advocacy for the gospel or the Church. In defiance of oligarchy, Tory cries about the "Church in Danger" went unheard. The Whigs purged the ministry of Tories, throttled parliamentary elections, and bridled the Church, with the silencing of Convocation in 1717. Hoadly was the symbol par excellence of this decay of the Church. It was this torpor that the Methodists (originally a high sacramental movement formed in royalist and High Church Oxford affiliated with Non-Juror William Law) lamented. Similarly, Tory-affiliated Evangelicals (Newton and Wilberforce) and the High Church movement that coalesced into the Tractarians equally damned the failure of the Whig-affiliated episcopal bench. Hoadly, a crippled striver of dubious theologian views (accusations that he was quasi-Arian or Deistic floated about) who promoted the Hobbist parliamentary apparatus which robbed England of its spirit in return for filthy lucre. As one polemicist put in lyric:
Then thus Great Salters-Hall shall ring, 
Thus, Thus, the Calves Head Club shall sing, 
Leviathan our God and King (Leviathan, or a Hymn to Poor Brother Ben, 1710)
This assessment has generally dominated Anglican historiography, whether internal or external to the communion. And Hoadly defenders have more often failed to fully recover his legacy. The first full length biography in recent years - Enlightenment Prelate - from priest-scholar William Gibson has only added to the confusion. Posed a Lockean empiricist, in defense of tolerance and Broad Church liberalism, Hoadly represented a celebrated advocate for the "English Enlightenment". Despite the use of the "Lockean" label, there are effectively zero references to Locke in Hoadly's work. Hoadly was believed to imbibe these values from his education in post-puritan Cambridge. However, unlike some of his peers, Hoadly fully rejected the creeping Cartesian rationalism, sneering it as "no more than the inventions of a very ingenious and luxuriant fancy having no foundation in the reality of things nor any correspondency to the certainty of facts" (quoted from Gibson, 51). For Gibson, the only alternative was the equal rejection of this Cartesian rationalism found in Newton and Locke. Thus, Hoadly is identified with this movement, despite the earlier underpinnings of so-called "Latitude men" originating from the rationalism of the "Cambridge Platonists" (another overly reified label. Hoadly's doctrine of sincerity, his willingness to treat with Dissenters, his friendly correspondence with Newtonian Samuel Clark (a subordinationist), all testify to Hoadly's allegiance to the Lockean tradition of humble, and fallible, epistemology. Gibson's work helped correct the image of Hoadly as a derelict time-server (his permanent crippling, demonstrated in the bishop's use of a scooter to walk, prevented frequent visitation). Nevertheless, Hoadly is simply given a positive valuation of an otherwise novel (and porto-modernist) clergyman. The vociferous preaching of High Churchman to be a martyr for the faith gave way to ecumenical relativity. Such is no more than what Hoadly's critics accused him of teaching behind the veil of preferment.

The rest of the essay will not treat much on Hoadly's personal foibles. He may very well indeed have been somewhat grasping for preferment (though Hoadly's endearment to Queen Caroline was in the good company of Joseph Butler and George Berkeley). However, the rest of this essay will focus on Hoadly's political and ecclesiastical theory. 

I contend that Hoadly's represents an alternative to the patriarchal High Churchmanship that has dominated most accounts of Anglicanism. Rather than an emphasis on noblesse oblige, common good Toryism (whether of a traditional or Red bent), royal absolutism, Hoadly represents what I term "Libertarian Anglicanism", an emphasis on natural law and the rights of the individual conscience within the Christian life. And this schema does not emerge from "Latitude" rationalism, ecumenism of post-puritan Dissent, or even Lockean politics (an often misunderstood category itself), but from the paradigms of Richard Hooker. It is from Hooker's thought that Hoadly derived his concern for the consent of the governed, the foundation of civic society from Natural Law (and thus restrained by the same), and a concern for limits of clerical authority to control the individual Christian's conscience.

To begin, let's dispel more falsehoods surrounding Hoadly. He was in no way relativistic about the Church of England's polity. He recognized that the original foundation of Christ's Church was three-tiered, constituted of bishops, priests, and deacons. When the Apostles died, the bishops succeeded the Apostles, with their subordinate priests fulfilling their prior role. However, the historic episcopacy is not necessary to salvation. Hoadly recognized the legitimacy of Continental Presbyterianism, which had to act to preserve the Gospel against hostile bishops. Nevertheless, the Church of England rightly preserved this order, by God's grace, and was in no way defective. Thus, English Dissenters have no good reason to hold themselves apart from the Church of England. If they would follow the contours of his argument, Dissenters could not deny they had no reason for schism and should seek ordination from their local bishop (The Reasonableness of Conformity to the Church of England, 1703, 4-23). Per most Anglicans, with exception to the most vociferous Anglo-Catholics, Hoadly's point is to shore up the Church's bona fides as a legitimate, and Reformed, Church without denying church status to Presbyterians abroad. Simultaneously, Hoadly hopes to persuade Dissenters that they were in error without supposing that the misled were hell bound. Here is why sincerity is important: it allowed Hoadly, the minister, to show both charity and conviction. He did not recognize Dissent as having their own truth, yet he would not sentence them for their ignorance. God would not punish English Presbyterians for their belief that they were, indeed, worshiping Jesus Christ rightly. While Hoadly would later be excoriated for equivocating all faiths, his purpose was to recognize the difficulty of knowledge in a fragmented world of competing confessions. A Roman Christian may be in severe error for praying to angels and saints as mediators, but was such an error damnable? Would God not answer their prayers, even if misdirected? Rather than relativizing truth, it was prefiguring the problem many Christians would face as confessions came face to face. In this way, Hoadly is distinctly useful for Americans and the history of plurality among Christian confessions.

Hoadly spent much of his writing career defending the revolutionary settlement of 1688. In a nutshell: the succession of Roman Catholic James II, his increased use of royal dispensation (excepting the law) for conformity to the Church of England, and the birth of a son (who was to be raised a Catholic, unlike his older daughters, Mary and Anne) alienated much of England's governing class. While some recent literature has tried to revive James II's reputation as a monarch of toleration, it was clear to many of James' contemporaries that he was attempting to rebuild Rome within England. While not a satrap to Louis XIV's ambitions for universal monarchy, James II copied his absolutist modernizing. The Restoration, in many way, was not a repudiation of Cromwell's state-building, but a continuation. James II sought to build central bureaucracy to protect an expanding mercantile empire, increasing taxes to fund an army and navy. James' generally followed Tory blue-water strategy, focused on naval expansion and leaving the Continent to the growing power of the Bourbons. The Glorious Revolution was thus not simply a palace coup, or a religiously motivated putsch, but about the fundamental nature of the English constitution. If this state-building was to continue, under whose authority would it be done? Was it under the king alone, the father who had absolute right and rule over England, subject only to God? Or must the king be in consultation with the nation, manifest through the institution of Parliament? Was the king above the law, as its source? Or was he, even as chief magistrate, still subject to it? Did subjects have rights only to the extent that the king allowed? Or could subjects do more than petition God with tears and prayers?

The refusal to submit to James II found broad support. The "immortal seven", bishops who refused to read James' declaration of toleration, bore silent witness as they were held in the Tower. John Churchill, loyal to James during his illegitimate nephew's uprising in 1685, bolted as the Dutch Stadtholder, William (both James' nephew and son-in-law), landed at Torbay in response to an invitation. Whig and Tory both flocked to William, and James' eldest daughter Mary, to see James checked. The problem was how such could be held together with reigning political theories. Conveniently, James Stuart fled abroad, attempting to lose the royal seal (easily found on the banks of the Thames) and thus make legitimacy difficult. Instead, this flight made William king de facto, even if Parliament's recognition that James had abdicated was sketchy at best. There were many attempts to theorize this turn of events, as supporters of this revolutionary settlement (which recognized certain legal rights of Parliament that the crown had to respect) sought to justify their actions. The Non-Jurors, a group of churchmen and their faithful who had lost their dioceses and parishes for refusing to swear an oath to William and Mary as king and queen, haunted the discussion. For Tory partisans, such as William Sherlock, who argued that William had the throne by right of conquest, Non-Jurors had exposed the fiction. How did this not justify might-makes-right politics? Was Oliver Cromwell king, instead of Charles II? How was this theory not an invitation for the Hobbist Leviathan?

Hoadly had interceded strongly on behalf of the revolutionary settlement. But he did so in strongly Hookerian terms. From the parish of Peter Le Poer's, Hoadly penned his Original and the Institution of Civil Government (1710). Gibson, in his biography, acknowledged (citing J.P. Kenyon) that it was likely that Hoadly structured his work like Locke's Second Treatise on Civil Government (this point is the only place Hoadly could be said to draw on Locke). But it's helpful to acknowledge the context for this work, which only became popular later in the eighteenth-century. Locke was one of many Whigs who sought to rebut the patriarchal theory of Robert Filmer. Against the idea that the throne was inheritable, instituted as the right of fatherly primogeniture, Locke advanced a contractual commonwealth. Hoadly would do the same, and like Locke, would overwhelmingly cite Richard Hooker for his contentions.

To begin, Hoadly defined the Patriarchal scheme he attacked: "not only that Scheme which fixeth Absolute, Uncontrollable Authority in Adam and his Male-Line, according to Promogeniture down to the universal Deluge; and in Noah afterwards: but that Scheme likewise which is engrafted upon this; and which may more properly indeed be call'd the Scheme of Possession" (Original, 2-3) . In other words: Hoadly rejected any theory that attached royal right in the absolute rights of family, without any consultation with the people of the nation. Hoadly engaged in biblical exegesis to reject any attempt to ground England's kingship in the genealogy of Adam or any other biblical patriarchs. Hoadly, in contrast, claimed to defend the revolution, as a legitimate overthrow of a tyrant, in Hookerian terms (Original, preface). And per Hooker, the commonwealth is under natural law, which restrained kings as much as commoners. Hoadly explicitly denied that the revolutionary-settlement was done by "the People" in a democratic sense. It was not the right of the average tinker or tailor to decide, for himself, his governor. Such was mob-rule, the same anarchic and chaotic voice that cried out to crucify Christ (Original, 101-104). Instead, Hoadly hoped to defend a firmer basis of monarchy than jurists combing genealogical records to prove the Stuarts were related to the Tablet of Nations in Genesis (Original, 109-110). Such not only ruined England, but made it unstable, opening the pathway to a Cromwellian dictatorship.

Hoadly offered, instead, Hooker's principles of government. Hooker had defended the rights and responsibilities of all souls in the commonwealth, including the king. Yes, the subject must obey the right to rule of the king, but the king himself must be obedient to Natural Law and the nation's constitution. Kingship was not essential to all forms of government, since human magistrates may adjust their own nation's form of government. Nevertheless, absolutists abhorred such a system and would likely chase Hooker out of the Church as an atheistic deist (Original, 131-137). Instead, citing Hooker, civil government was distinct from patriarchal authority. The king was not the great father, who possessed absolute natural right over his children-subjects. Rather, it was from a historical compact between subjects to determine, or change, the form of government under which they lived. Monarchs had no right to ruin the society they had been determined to defend and protect, including the lives and property of their subjects (Original, 137-140). Civil government was temporary, formed to achieve certain aims. These were not absolute in their own right, or possess any utopian aspirations. Instead, Hoadly defended the purpose of civil government to defend man's natural right to exercise his "Reason, Wisdom, and Deliberation", as he quests to closer conform to God. Despite sneers that Hoadly was a Hobbist in service of Leviathan, Hoadly denied the state could ever create or guarantee the supreme happiness of man (Original, 154). Despite the screeching of patriarchal absolutists, it was precisely in disentangling the civil from the familial which promoted both. Hierarchy was natural, found in the father's authority over his son, and did not depend on the determinations of any particular civil government (Original, 162-163). These arguments were not unlike similar Whig arguments from Locke or James Tyrrell against Filmer. However, the self-conscious use of Hooker revealed how radical traditional defenses of the Church had become. It was not patriarchal High Churchmen, but a so-called "Latitude" Churchman like Hoadly, which defended Hooker's classic defense of both Church and state from puritan attacks.

This defense of natural law, and the constitutional nature of all civil government, does not empower rebellion. In contrast, Hoadly excoriated rebellion in biblical terms: sinful and deserving of God's wrath. Nevertheless, what took place in the Glorious Revolution was not a rebellion. Why? Because rebels are those who oppose the ends of civil government: public peace and common good. Such realization was natural, open to all peoples, part of God's natural revelation (Original, 178-179). Hoadly concluded this second section with an appeal that all churchmen return to Hooker's scheme. For it was in Hooker that one clearly saw both the foundations of the Church of England as well as England's civil government (Original, 199-200). In short, Hoadly admonished the people against slavish submission to any absolute authority. And he did so through Hooker's defense of the English commonwealth. It was not for kings to claim patriarchal authority or be above the law. Even if the king was a father, a father has no right to murder his child. The natural law of self-defense and self-preservation triumphed over any royal prescription, no matter how thunderous. It was part of the heritage of the Church of England to refuse tyranny, whether of state or the Church.

It's the latter where Hoadly's defense of sincerity enters in. Against High Churchman (not the same as Non-Juror) and future Jacobite, Francis Atterbury, Hoadly turned against the concept of Passive Obedience. This doctrine not only advanced the obligation for Christians to obey civil authority, but made complete submission to the crown (as the source of all law and government) necessary for faith. High Churchmen like Atterbury would even claim that this doctrine was what set the Church of England apart as the most faithful of her sister churches. Hoadly excoriated this slavish spirit. Would not Nero and Caligula leapt for such docile subjects, passively allowing kings to act as they wanted with no opposition? Would this not make the most degenerate and absurd interpretation of Romans 13, allowing those professing to be king (with a ministry of jurists manufacturing genealogy) do as they willed? Such was to make a mockery of St. Paul (Response to Atterbury, 19-44). Instead, Romans 13 should be understood not only as a moral command, but a moral command in response to a definition. Government was not whoever happened to posses authority, but one who had the office to reward good and punish evil. This applied to both superior and inferior magistrates, not just the king (Response to Atterbury, 74-75). Christians had no injunction to actively serve, or passively suffer, a government which had ceased to act as a government (Response to Atterbury, 90-92). In a way, such is similar to doctrine of lesser magistrate, empowering lesser authorities to resist the supreme magistrate if it committed injustice. However, at the very least, it meant that Christians, according to Romans 13, had no reason to obey a government seeking to destroy them, or to disobey a lesser magistrate refusing to carry out violations of the law. Atterbury himself was a hypocrite, apparent in his abandonment of the revolutionary settlement (which he had accepted) for Jacobite scheming (brought to fruition in the botched invasion of 1715). In the end, Hoadly's schema is to strengthen civil authority in the sense that it can be known and restrained. Without such, one would be at the behest of your conscience, deciding which authority was legitimate. This was a problem George Berkeley, a Tory loyal to the Hanoverian succession, outlined. The conclusion is worth quoting in full: 
In morality the eternal rules of action have the same immutable universal truth with propositions in geometry. Neither of them depends on circumstances or accidents, being at all times and in all places, without limitation or exception, true. ' Thou shalt not resist the supreme civil power ' is no less constant and unalterable a rule, for modelling the behaviour of a subject toward the government, than 'multiply the height by half the base' is for measuring a triangle. And, as it would not be thought to detract from the universality of this mathematical rule that it did not exactly measure a field which was not an exact triangle, so ought it not to be thought an argument against the universality of the rule prescribing passive obedience that it does not reach a man's practice in all cases where a government is unhinged, or the supreme power disputed. There must be a triangle, and you must use your senses to know this, before there is room for applying your mathematical rule. And there must be a civil government, and you must know in whose hands it is lodged, before the moral precept takes place. But, where the supreme power is ascertained, we should no more doubt of our submission to it, than we would doubt of the way to measure a figure we know to be a triangle. 

In the Various Changes and Fluctuations of Government, it is impossible to prevent that Controversies shou'd sometimes arise concerning the Seat of the Supreme Power. And in such Cases Subjects cannot be Denied the Liberty of Judging for Themselves, or of taking part with some, and opposing others, according to the best of their Judgments; all which is Consistent with an exact Observation of their Duty, so long as, when the Constitution is clear in the Point, and the Object of their Submission undoubted, no Pretext of In|terest, Friends, or the Publick Good, can make them depart from it. In short, it is acknowledged, that the Precept enjoyning Non-Resistance is Limited to particular Objects, but not to particular Occasions. And in this it is like all other Moral Negative Duties, which consider'd as general Pro|positions, do admit of Limitations and Restrictions, in order to a distinct Definition of the Duty; but what is once known to be a Duty of that sort, can never become otherwise by any good or ill Effect, Circumstance, or Event whatsoever. And in Truth if it were not so, if there were no General Inflexible Rules, but all Negative as well as Positive Duties might be Dispensed with, and Warpt to Serve particular Interests and Occasions, there were an end of all Morality. (Berkeley, Discourse of Passive Obedience, LIII-LIV)

But Atterbury was not interested in the chaos of an unhinged conscience. Rather, he, as many High Churchmen were interested, in making sure laity formed their conscience in accordance with the clergy. From his pulpit at St Peter Le Poer, Hoadly attacked this attempt to usurp the conscience from sacerdotal tyrants. Hoadly rejected the power-based nature of this arrangement: "And, again, Supposing this Doctrine [passive obedience] to be as They represent it, You have the same liberty to differ from this point, which these Gentlemen themselves have in many Others, upon which equal weight is laid. They, of all Persons living must never reproach You, till They can shew You, their Scheme of Church-Authority, Sacerdotal Powers, Regular Successions, Authoritative Benedictions, and Absolutions, or their Notions of many other Points, not to have been condemn'd even with Zeal by the Church of our First Reformers" (A Preservative Against the Principles & Practices of the Nonjurors, 18). In other words, which is apparent to most contemporary Anglicans, there's a wide divergence of what "obedience to the Church" means. Those who trumpet "tradition" tend to ignore the writings of the earliest Reformers. The point isn't that it's all a free-for-all, which is precisely what this sacerdotal determination of doctrine would unleash. Rather, it's acknowledging the question of authority, which the Reformers themselves introduced through their efforts to restore the Gospel.  The authority of the priest derived from his obedience to the parameters of his office, not self-derived. A bad priest was to be resisted if he sought tyrannize the conscience, requiring what was not in scripture to be saved. The authority of the bishop was to be a shepherd, not a lord. He was a teacher and instructor, not a master.

Such was why Hoadly prized sincerity. It was not that we all had our own truths, but that one's benefit from believing a doctrine could not be imposed from the outside. One could persuade, censure, and instruct, but one could not compel saving belief. Instead, the result would only be hypocrisy. Such was what motivated Hoadly's later attack on the sacramental Test Act, which made participation in the Church of England's eucharist necessary for political office. This requirement not only politicized the sacred rite, but it was useless. It was well known Dissenters engaged in partial conformity, showing up for the necessary eucharistic participation to meet the law. This requirement did nothing to create love for the Church and its institutions (c.f. The Common Rights of Subjects, Defended: And the Nature of the Sacramental Test, considered). Sincerity was to acknowledge the limits of human knowledge, that God would be gracious with limits of error when it came to acknowledging extra-biblical formula. 

Hence Hoadly's association with Christological heterodoxy. While he adhered to the Athanasian creed, he thought its damnatory clauses were a mistake, since Nicaean orthodoxy was never explicit in the New Testament (The Reasonableness of Conformity, 134). This reality does not make it less true, only that one can not damn those who erroneous oppose or question it. One may even vigorously oppose it, but did that give a priest the right to state, infallibly, that the holder of said error was in a state of damnation? Difficulties among Anglicans over the normative status of the creeds and councils has only underlined this problem more and more. Anglo-Catholics, if they were consistent, would have to damn their peers who rejected iconodoulia per the strictures of Nicaea II. The huffing and puffing of academically inclined seminarians notwithstanding, Christians of all stripes hold a wide variety of views on important theological issues (from Christology to eschatology). Are they damned for their errors? And should the Church have the power to threaten such? Hoadly disagreed and opted for engagement that would not breed resentment. Again, the point isn't about the existence of error, or the state of truth, but the Christian's use of wisdom and discernment about the Final Judgement. Should one evangelize a credobaptist in the same vein as one evangelized a Muslim or an atheist? Hoadly here offers a relevant touchstone.

The importance of Hoadly, in short, is to defend the liberties of Natural Law. It should certainly undo the pseudo-anxiety, and huffy conservatism, of Anglicans who feel the need to disavow the American Revolution. Instead, many priests in the Church of Virginia (including relatively orthodox lay Anglicans like Patrick Henry or John Randolph of Roanoke) supported opposition to tyranny. Rather than spiritual Jacobitism, appealing to a "king over the water" who has neither authority nor reality, Anglicans can advance the American tradition of liberty. There is an American Anglican tradition of romantic resistance in a figure such as Richard Dana, who rejected the spirit of the American Revolution. But it should be no surprise that a royalism without a king, an Anglicanism as a retreat from American society, gave birth to Fourierism of Richard Jr., a political ally of the socialist unitarianism of Horace Greeley. This romantic veneration of authority often breeds the fantastic support for tyrannical regimes of all stripes. The warm paternal embrace of conservative Christian Democracy has marked many Anglican converts and self-professed "Reformed Catholics", the very same political apparatus has turned Western Europe into a concentration camp. Crowing for authority and tradition has brought about passive submission to the grasping authority of the state. The cry of post-liberals everywhere has been "common good! common good!", but these same have surrendered (and often become advocates) of an increasing strained biomedical security state apparatus. This Spiritual Jacobitism leads nowhere but an empty-headed submission (and enthusiasm) to statism.

Hoadly's faithful commitment to Hooker opens up a Libertarian Anglicanism, one that recognizes natural law (including natural hierarchy) as the framework out of which civil governments arise. No authority is absolute or responsible to God alone. Instead, the commonwealth- republic - a government restrained by law and custom and aware of its derivation from the created contours of God's world, prohibits both clericalism and statism. Instead, Anglicans would be better served by returning to covenantal paradigms derived from Hooker and applied to shape the old Whig settlement of constitutional monarchy. Anglicans would be better served from Gladstonian liberalism (The Great Commoner was both High Church and Evangelical) rather the paternalistic social democracy of Disraeli. American Anglicans don't need to lament their separation from the Crown, but rejoice in the libertarian tradition found throughout American history, which prized limitations of civil and central authority on behalf of the local, the ecclesial and the familial. Rather than a villain or cretin, Benjamin Hoadly should be venerated for his full-throated defense of the Elizabethan settlement, a vision of what "Reformed Catholic" should mean.